Search the FAQ Archives

3 - A - B - C - D - E - F - G - H - I - J - K - L - M
N - O - P - Q - R - S - T - U - V - W - X - Y - Z
faqs.org - Internet FAQ Archives

rec.puzzles Archive (logic), part 22 of 35

( Part1 - Part2 - Part3 - Part4 - Part5 )
[ Usenet FAQs | Web FAQs | Documents | RFC Index | Forum ]
Archive-name: puzzles/archive/logic/part1
Last-modified: 17 Aug 1993
Version: 4

See reader questions & answers on this topic! - Help others by sharing your knowledge
==> logic/29.p <==
Three people check into a hotel.  They pay $30 to the manager and go
to their room.  The manager finds out that the room rate is $25 and
gives $5 to the bellboy to return.  On the way to the room the bellboy
reasons that $5 would be difficult to share among three people so
he pockets $2 and gives $1 to each person.

Now each person paid $10 and got back $1.  So they paid $9 each,
totalling $27.  The bellboy has $2, totalling $29.

Where is the remaining dollar?

==> logic/29.s <==
Each person paid $9, totalling $27.  The manager has $25 and the bellboy $2.
The bellboy's $2 should be added to the manager's $25 or subtracted from
the tenants' $27, not added to the tenants' $27.

==> logic/ages.p <==
1) Ten years from now Tim will be twice as old as Jane was when Mary was 
   nine times as old as Tim.

2) Eight years ago, Mary was half as old as Jane will be when Jane is one year
   older than Tim will be at the time when Mary will be five times as old as 
   Tim will be two years from now.

3) When Tim was one year old, Mary was three years older than Tim will be when 
   Jane is three times as old as Mary was six years before the time when Jane 
   was half as old as Tim will be when Mary will be ten years older than Mary 
   was when Jane was one-third as old as Tim will be when Mary will be three 
   times as old as she was when Jane was born.

                             HOW OLD ARE THEY NOW?

==> logic/ages.s <==
The solution: Tim is 3, Jane is 8, and Mary is 15.  A little grumbling
is in order here, as clue number 1 leads to the situation a year and a
half ago, when Tim was 1 1/2, Jane was 6 1/2, and Mary was 13 1/2.

This sort of problem is easy if you write down a set of equations.  Let
t be the year that Tim was born, j be the year that Jane was born, m be
the year that Mary was born, and y be the current year.  As indefinite
years come up, let y1, y2, ... be the indefinite years.  Then the
equations are


y + 10 - t = 2 (y1 - j)
y1 - m = 9 (y1 - t)

y - 8 - m = 1/2 (y2 - j)
y2 - j = 1 + y3 - t
y3 - m = 5 (y + 2 - t)

t + 1 - m = 3 + y4 - t
y4 - j = 3 (y5 - 6 - m)
y5 - j = 1/2 (y6 - t)
y6 - m = 10 + y7 - m
y7 - j = 1/3 (y8 - t)
y8 - m = 3 (j - m)

t = y - 3
j = y - 8
m = y - 15

==> logic/attribute.p <==
All the items in the first list share a particular attribute.  The second
list is of some items lacking the attribute.

Set#1
    with:  battery, key, yeast, bookmark
    w/out: stapler, match, Rubik's cube, pill bottle

Set#2
    with:  Rubik's cube, chess set, electrical wiring, compass needle
    w/out: clock, rope, tic-tac-toe, pencil sharpener

Set#3:
    with:  koosh, small intestine, Yorkshire Terrier, Christmas Tree
    w/out: toothbrush, oak chair, soccer ball, icicle

Points to realize:
1.
 There may be exceptions to any item on the list, for instance a particular
 clock may share the properties of the 'with' list of problem two, BUT MOST
 ORDINARY clocks do not.  All the properties apply the vast majority of the
 the items mentioned.  Extraordinary exceptions should be ignored.

2.
 Pay the most attention to the 'with' list.  The 'without' list is only
 present to eliminate various 'stupid' answers.

==> logic/attribute.s <==
The attribute puzzle format is a traditional format in math education.
It occurs in logic materials developed in the sixties by EDC in Boston,
with visual objects. Example:

these are gloops: A B C D E 
these are not gloops: F G J L N
which of these are gloops? O P Q R S

Set#1
    with:  battery, key, yeast, bookmark
    w/out: stapler, match, Rubik's cube, pill bottle

Needs to be placed inside something else when used for its usual purpose.

Set#2
    with:  Rubik's cube, chess set, electrical wiring, compass needle
    w/out: clock, rope, tic-tac-toe, pencil sharpener

Uses color to distinguish between otherwise identical parts.

Set#3:
    with:  koosh, small intestine, Yorkshire Terrier, Christmas Tree
    w/out: toothbrush, oak chair, soccer ball, icicle

Villiform.

==> logic/bookworm.p <==
A bookworm eats from the first page of an encyclopedia to the last
page.  The bookworm eats in a straight line.  The encyclopedia consists
of ten 1000-page volumes and is sitting on a bookshelf in the usual
order.  Not counting covers, title pages, etc., how many pages does the
bookworm eat through?

==> logic/bookworm.s <==
On a book shelf the first page of the first volume is on the "inside"
  __                             __
B|  |                           |  |F
A|1 |...........................|10|R
C|  |                           |  |O
K|  |                           |  |N
 |  |                           |  |T
  ----------------------------------
so the bookworm eats only through the cover of the first volume, then 8 times
1000 pages of Volumes 2 - 9, then through the cover to the 1st page of Vol 10.
He eats 8,000 pages.

If the bookworm ate the first page and the last page, it ate 8,004 pages.

==> logic/boxes.p <==
Which Box Contains the Gold?

Two boxes are labeled "A" and "B".  A sign on box A says "The sign
on box B is true and the gold is in box A".  A sign on box B says
"The sign on box A is false and the gold is in box A".  Assuming there
is gold in one of the boxes, which box contains the gold?

==> logic/boxes.s <==
The problem cannot be solved with the information given.

The sign on box A says "The sign on box B is true and the gold is in box A".
The sign on box B says "The sign on box A is false and the gold is in box A".
The following argument can be made: If the statement on box A is true, then
the statement on box B is true, since that is what the statement on box A
says.  But the statement on box B states that the statement on box A is false,
which contradicts the original assumption.  Therefore, the statement on box A
must be false.  This implies that either the statement on box B is false or
that the gold is in box B.  If the statement on box B is false, then either
the statement on box A is true (which it cannot be) or the gold is in box B.
Either way, the gold is in box B.

However, there is a hidden assumption in this argument: namely, that
each statement must be either true or false.  This assumption leads to
paradoxes, for example, consider the statement: "This statement is
false."  If it is true, it is false; if it is false, it is true.  The
only way out of the paradox is to deny that the statement is either true
or false and label it meaningless instead.  Both of the statements on the
boxes are therefore meaningless and nothing can be concluded from them.

In general, statements about the truth of other statements lead to
contradictions.  Tarski invented metalanguages to avoid this problem.
To avoid paradox, a statement about the truth of a statement in a language
must be made in the metalanguage of the language.

Common sense dictates that this problem cannot be solved with the information
given.  After all, how can we deduce which box contains the gold simply by
reading statements written on the outside of the box?  Suppose we deduce that
the gold is in box B by whatever line of reasoning we choose.  What is to stop
us from simply putting the gold in box A, regardless of what we deduced?
(cf. Smullyan, "What Is the Name of This Book?", Prentice-Hall, 1978,	#70)

==> logic/camel.p <==
An Arab sheikh tells his two sons to race their camels to a distant
city to see who will inherit his fortune.  The one whose camel is
slower will win.  The brothers, after wandering aimlessly for days, ask
a wise man for advise.  After hearing the advice they jump on the
camels and race as fast as they can to the city.  What does the wise
man say?

==> logic/camel.s <==
The wiseman tells them to switch camels.

==> logic/centrifuge.p <==
You are a biochemist, working with a 12-slot centrifuge.  This is a gadget
that has 12 equally spaced slots around a central axis, in which you can
place chemical samples you want centrifuged.  When the machine is turned on,
the samples whirl around the central axis and do their thing.

To ensure that the samples are evenly mixed, they must be distributed in the
12 slots such that the centrifuge is balanced evenly.  For example, if you
wanted to mix 4 samples, you could place them in slots 12, 3, 6 and 9
(assuming the slots are numbered from 1 to 12 like a clock).

Problem:  Can you use the centrifuge to mix 5 samples?

==> logic/centrifuge.s <==
The superposition of any two solutions is yet another solution, so given
that the factors > 1 of 12 (2, 3, 4, 6, 12) are all solutions, the
only thing to check about, for example, the proposed solution 2+3 is
that not all ways of combining 2 & 3 would have centrifuge tubes
from one subsolution occupying the slot for one of the tubes in
another solution.  For the case 2+3, there is no problem:  Place 3
tubes, one in every 4th position, then place the 4th and 5th
diametrically opposed (each will end up in a slot adjacent to one of
the first 3 tubes).  The obvious generalization is, what are the
numbers of tubes that cannot be balanced?  Observing that there are
solutions for 2,3,4,5,6 tubes and that if X has a solution, 12-X has
also one (obtained by swapping tubes and holes), it is obvious that
1 and 11 are the only cases without solutions.

Here is how this problem is often solved in practice:  A dummy tube
is added to produce a total number of tubes that is easy to balance.
For example, if you had to centrifuge just one sample, you'd add a
second tube opposite it for balance.

==> logic/chain.p <==
What is the least number of links you can cut in a chain of 21 links to be able
to give someone all possible number of links up to 21?

==> logic/chain.s <==
Two.

	OOO C OOOOO C OOOOOOOOOOO
(where Os are chained unbroken links, and the Cs are the unchained broken links)

And equivalently:

	OOO C OOOOOO C OOOOOOOOOO

==> logic/children.p <==
A man walks into a bar, orders a drink, and starts chatting with the
bartender.  After a while, he learns that the bartender has three
children.  "How old are your children?" he asks.  "Well," replies the
bartender, "the product of their ages is 72."  The man thinks for a
moment and then says, "that's not enough information."  "All right,"
continues the bartender, "if you go outside and look at the building
number posted over the door to the bar, you'll see the sum of the
ages."  The man steps outside, and after a few moments he reenters and
declares, "Still not enough!"  The bartender smiles and says, "My
youngest just loves strawberry ice cream."

How old are the children?

A variant of the problem is for the sum of the ages to be 13 and the
product of the ages to be the number posted over the door.  In this
case, it is the oldest that loves ice cream.

Then how old are they?


==> logic/children.s <==
First, determine all the ways that three ages can multiply together to get 72:

72  1  1        (quite a feat for the bartender)
36  2  1
24  3  1
18  4  1
18  2  2
12  6  1
12  3  2
9  4  2
9  8  1
8  3  3
6  6  2
6  4  3

As the man says, that's not enough information; there are many possibilities.
So the bartender tells him where to find the sum of the ages--the man now knows
the sum even though we don't.  Yet he still insists that there isn't enough
info.  This must mean that there are two permutations with the same sum;
otherwise the man could have easily deduced the ages.

The only pair of permutations with the same sum are 8 3 3 and 6 6 2, which both
add up to 14 (the bar's address).  Now the bartender mentions his
"youngest"--telling us that there is one child who is younger than the other
two.  This is impossible with 8 3 3--there are two 3 year olds.  Therefore the
ages of the children are 6, 6, and 2.

Pedants have objected that the problem is insoluble because there could be
a youngest between two three year olds (even twins are not born exactly at
the same time).  However, the word "age" is frequently used to denote the
number of years since birth.  For example, I am the same age as my wife,
even though technically she is a few months older than I am.  And using the
word "youngest" to mean "of lesser age" is also in keeping with common parlance.
So I think the solution is fine as stated.

In the sum-13 variant, the possibilities are:

11  1  1
10  2  1
9  3  1
9  2  2
8  4  1
8  3  2
7  5  1
7  4  2
7  3  3
6  6  1
6  5  2
6  4  3

The two that remain are 9 2 2 and 6 6 1 (both products equal 36).  The
final bit of info (oldest child) indicates that there is only one
child with the highest age.  This cancels out the 6 6 1 combination, leaving
the childern with ages of 9, 2, and 2.

==> logic/condoms.p <==
How can a man have mutually safe sex with three women with only two condoms?
How can three men have mutually safe sex with one woman with two condoms?

==> logic/condoms.s <==
Use both condoms on the first woman.  Take off the outer condom (turning it
inside-out in the process) and set it aside.  Use the inner condom alone on
the second woman.  Put the outer condom back on.  Use it on the third woman.

First man uses both condoms.  Take off the outer condom (do NOT reverse
it) and have second man use it.  First man takes off the inner condom
(turning it inside-out).  Third man puts on this condom, followed by
second man's condom.

==> logic/dell.p <==
How can I solve logic puzzles (e.g., as published by Dell) automatically?

==> logic/dell.s <==
#include	<setjmp.h>

#define	EITHER		if (S[1] = S[0], ! setjmp((S++)->jb)) {
#define	OR		} else EITHER
#define	REJECT		longjmp((--S)->jb, 1)
#define	END_EITHER	} else REJECT;

/* values in tmat: */
#define	T_UNK	0
#define	T_YES	1
#define	T_NO	2

#define	Val(t1,t2)	(S->tmat[t1][t2])
#define	CLASS(x)		\
		(((x) / NUM_ITEM) * NUM_ITEM)
#define	EVERY_TOKEN(x)		\
		(x = 0; x < TOT_TOKEN; x++)
#define	EVERY_ITEM(x, class)	\
		(x = CLASS(class); x < CLASS(class) + NUM_ITEM; x++)

#define	BEGIN						\
struct state {						\
	char	tmat[TOT_TOKEN][TOT_TOKEN];		\
	jmp_buf jb;					\
} States[100], *S = States;				\
							\
main()							\
{							\
	int	token;					\
							\
	for EVERY_TOKEN(token)				\
		yes(token, token);			\
	EITHER

/* Here is the problem-specific data */
#define	NUM_ITEM	5
#define	NUM_CLASS	6
#define	TOT_TOKEN	(NUM_ITEM * NUM_CLASS)

#define	HOUSE_0		0
#define	HOUSE_1		1
#define	HOUSE_2		2
#define	HOUSE_3		3
#define	HOUSE_4		4

#define	ENGLISH		5
#define	SPANISH		6
#define	NORWEG		7
#define	UKRAIN		8
#define	JAPAN		9

#define	GREEN		10
#define	RED		11
#define	IVORY		12
#define	YELLOW		13
#define	BLUE		14

#define	COFFEE		15
#define	TEA		16
#define	MILK		17
#define	OJUICE		18
#define	WATER		19

#define	DOG		20
#define	SNAIL		21
#define	FOX		22
#define	HORSE		23
#define	ZEBRA		24

#define	OGOLD		25
#define	PLAYER		26
#define	CHESTER		27
#define	LSTRIKE		28
#define	PARLIA		29

char *names[] = {
	"HOUSE_0", "HOUSE_1", "HOUSE_2", "HOUSE_3", "HOUSE_4",
	"ENGLISH", "SPANISH", "NORWEG", "UKRAIN", "JAPAN",
	"GREEN", "RED", "IVORY", "YELLOW", "BLUE",
	"COFFEE", "TEA", "MILK", "OJUICE", "WATER",
	"DOG", "SNAIL", "FOX", "HORSE", "ZEBRA",
	"OGOLD", "PLAYER", "CHESTER", "LSTRIKE", "PARLIA",
};

	BEGIN

	yes(ENGLISH, RED);	/* Clue 1 */
	yes(SPANISH, DOG);	/* Clue 2 */
	yes(COFFEE, GREEN);	/* Clue 3 */
	yes(UKRAIN, TEA);	/* Clue 4 */

	EITHER			/* Clue 5 */
		yes(IVORY, HOUSE_0);
		yes(GREEN, HOUSE_1);
	OR
		yes(IVORY, HOUSE_1);
		yes(GREEN, HOUSE_2);
	OR
		yes(IVORY, HOUSE_2);
		yes(GREEN, HOUSE_3);
	OR
		yes(IVORY, HOUSE_3);
		yes(GREEN, HOUSE_4);
	END_EITHER

	yes(OGOLD, SNAIL);	/* Clue 6 */
	yes(PLAYER, YELLOW);	/* Clue 7 */
	yes(MILK, HOUSE_2);	/* Clue 8 */
	yes(NORWEG, HOUSE_0);	/* Clue 9 */

	EITHER			/* Clue 10 */
		yes(CHESTER, HOUSE_0);
		yes(FOX, HOUSE_1);
	OR
		yes(CHESTER, HOUSE_4);
		yes(FOX, HOUSE_3);
	OR
		yes(CHESTER, HOUSE_1);
		EITHER	yes(FOX, HOUSE_0);
		OR	yes(FOX, HOUSE_2);
		END_EITHER
	OR
		yes(CHESTER, HOUSE_2);
		EITHER	yes(FOX, HOUSE_1);
		OR	yes(FOX, HOUSE_3);
		END_EITHER
	OR
		yes(CHESTER, HOUSE_3);
		EITHER	yes(FOX, HOUSE_2);
		OR	yes(FOX, HOUSE_4);
		END_EITHER
	END_EITHER

	EITHER			/* Clue 11 */
		yes(PLAYER, HOUSE_0);
		yes(HORSE, HOUSE_1);
	OR
		yes(PLAYER, HOUSE_4);
		yes(HORSE, HOUSE_3);
	OR
		yes(PLAYER, HOUSE_1);
		EITHER	yes(HORSE, HOUSE_0);
		OR	yes(HORSE, HOUSE_2);
		END_EITHER
	OR
		yes(PLAYER, HOUSE_2);
		EITHER	yes(HORSE, HOUSE_1);
		OR	yes(HORSE, HOUSE_3);
		END_EITHER
	OR
		yes(PLAYER, HOUSE_3);
		EITHER	yes(HORSE, HOUSE_2);
		OR	yes(HORSE, HOUSE_4);
		END_EITHER
	END_EITHER

	yes(LSTRIKE, OJUICE);	/* Clue 12 */
	yes(JAPAN, PARLIA);	/* Clue 13 */

	EITHER			/* Clue 14 */
		yes(NORWEG, HOUSE_0);
		yes(BLUE, HOUSE_1);
	OR
		yes(NORWEG, HOUSE_4);
		yes(BLUE, HOUSE_3);
	OR
		yes(NORWEG, HOUSE_1);
		EITHER	yes(BLUE, HOUSE_0);
		OR	yes(BLUE, HOUSE_2);
		END_EITHER
	OR
		yes(NORWEG, HOUSE_2);
		EITHER	yes(BLUE, HOUSE_1);
		OR	yes(BLUE, HOUSE_3);
		END_EITHER
	OR
		yes(NORWEG, HOUSE_3);
		EITHER	yes(BLUE, HOUSE_2);
		OR	yes(BLUE, HOUSE_4);
		END_EITHER
	END_EITHER

/* End of problem-specific data */

		solveit();
	OR
		printf("All solutions found\n");
		exit(0);
	END_EITHER
}

no(a1, a2)
{
	int	non1, non2, token;

	if (Val(a1, a2) == T_YES)
		REJECT;
	else if (Val(a1, a2) == T_UNK) {
		Val(a1, a2) = T_NO;
		no(a2, a1);
		non1 = non2 = -1;

		for EVERY_ITEM(token, a1)
			if (Val(token, a2) != T_NO)
				if (non1 == -1)
					non1 = token;
				else
					break;
		if (non1 == -1)
			REJECT;
		else if (token == CLASS(a1) + NUM_ITEM)
			yes(non1, a2);

		for EVERY_TOKEN(token)
			if (Val(token, a1) == T_YES)
				no(a2, token);
	}
}

yes(a1, a2)
{
	int	token;

	if (Val(a1, a2) == T_NO)
		REJECT;
	else if (Val(a1, a2) == T_UNK) {
		Val(a1, a2) = T_YES;
		yes(a2, a1);
		for EVERY_ITEM(token, a1)
			if (token != a1)
				no(token, a2);
		for EVERY_TOKEN(token)
			if (Val(token, a1) == T_YES)
				yes(a2, token);
			else if (Val(token, a1) == T_NO)
				no(a2, token);
	}
}

solveit()
{
	int	token, tok2;

	for EVERY_TOKEN(token)
		for (tok2 = token; tok2 < TOT_TOKEN; tok2++)
			if (Val(token, tok2) == T_UNK) {
				EITHER
					yes(token, tok2);
				OR
					no(token, tok2);
				END_EITHER;
				return solveit();
			}
	printf("Solution:\n");
	for EVERY_ITEM(token, 0) {
		for (tok2 = NUM_ITEM; tok2 < TOT_TOKEN; tok2++)
			if (Val(token, tok2) == T_YES)
				printf("\t%s %s\n",names[token],names[tok2]);
		printf("\n");
	}
	REJECT;
}

---
james@crc.ricoh.com (James Allen)

==> logic/elimination.p <==
97 baseball teams participate in an annual state tournament.
The way the champion is chosen for this tournament is by the same old
elimination schedule. That is, the 97 teams are to be divided into
pairs, and the two teams of each pair play against each other.
After a team is eliminated from each pair, the winners would
be again divided into pairs, etc.  How many games must be played
to determine a champion?

==> logic/elimination.s <==
In order to determine a winner all but one team must lose.
Therefore there must be at least 96 games.

==> logic/flip.p <==
How can a toss be called over the phone (without requiring trust)?

==> logic/flip.s <==
A flips a coin.  If the result is heads, A multiplies 2 prime numbers
containing about 90 digits; if the result is tails, A multiplies 3
prime numbers containing about 60 digits.  A tells B the result of the
multiplication.  B now calls either heads or tails and tells A.  A then
supplies B with the original numbers to verify the flip.

Consider what is involved in multiplying 90 digit numbers.  Using the method
of long multiplication that we all learned in grade school, you have maybe
90 or so strings of 90 characters (or "digits") each.  That's no problem for
a computer to deal with.  The magnitude of the number represented isn't
much of a factor; we're only manipulating the string of digits.

Consider what is involved in factoring 90 digit numbers.  There are of course,
little tricks for determining factorability by small integers which we all
learned in grade school.  (Is the last digit even?  Is the sum of all the
digits divisible by 9?  And so on.)  But these are of little use in factoring
large numbers with large factors.  In fact, there is no essentially better
method than checking every number smaller that the number to be factored and
seeing if it one divides the other evenly.  We means we could be checking some
100,000,000,000,000,000,000,000,000,000,000,000,000,000,000,000,000,000,000,000
nummbers.  This is very hard to do, even for a supercomputer.  Here, the
number of digits this number has is of little consequence.  It is the
magnitude of the number that we have to worry about, and there just isn't 
enough time in the world to do this properly.

Where does A find a list of 60- and 90- digit prime numbers?  Well, that's not
to hard to come by.  The simplest method to find a few prime numbers is simply
to choose a 90-digit number (or 60-digit number, as the case warrants)
randomly, and check to see if it is prime.  You won't have to wait too long
before you stumble across a prime number.

"But wait!" you cry.  "I thought you just said it was incredibly difficult
to factor large numbers.  If that's the case, then how are you going to know
if the number you randomly choose is prime?"  A good question.  Here we enter
into the strange an wacky world of number theory.  It turns out (and I won't
explain how unless someone asks) there are "probabalistic" algorithms,
which depend on us choosing numbers at random.  There are probablistic
algorithms that when given a prime number, will quickly tell us that it is
a prime number, and when given a composite number, will either tell us that
it is a composite number (with very, very high probability) or will tell us
that it is a prime number (with very, very low probability.)  What's the use
of an algorithm that only returns the right answer "with very, very high
probability?"  Well, we can make this probability as high as we want, just by
running the algorithm longer.  In fact, it is within our technological
abilities to quickly run this algorithm for 90-digit numbers so that the
probability of it giving a wrong answer is less than the probability of a
cosmic ray striking a vital part of the computer at some vital time and causing
the computer to spit out the wrong answer anyway.  That's what I mean by "very,
very high."

==> logic/flowers.p <==
How many flowers do I have if all of them are roses except two, all of
them are tulips except two, and all of them are daisies except two?

==> logic/flowers.s <==
There are two solutions:

Three flowers: rose, tulip, daisy
Two flowers:   carnation, geranium

==> logic/friends.p <==
Any group of 6 or more contains either 3 mutual friends or 3 mutual strangers.
Prove it.

==> logic/friends.s <==
Take a person X.  Of the five other people, there must either be at least three
acquaintances of X or at least three strangers of X.  Assume wlog that X has
three strangers A,B,C.  Unless A,B,C is the required triad of acquaintances,
they must include a pair of strangers, wlog A,B.  Then X,A,B is the required
triad of strangers, QED.

==> logic/hofstadter.p <==
In first-order logic, find a predicate P(x) which means "x is a power of 10."

==> logic/hofstadter.s <==
Well, one summer, I decided to tackle the problem. Not having any great
knowledge of number theory, I used a more brute force approach. Note
that for greater comprehensibility, I have broken the resulting formula
up into several stages, but it would not be difficult to put it
back together into one vast formula:

{e is prime:}
PRIME(e) := 
   ~Eb:Ec:((b+2)*(c+2) = e)

{if e is a prime, true iff a is a power of e:}
PPOWER(a,e) :=
   Ab:Ac:((b*c = a) -> ((b = 1) or (Ed: (e*d) = b)))

{if e is a prime, and a is a power of e, true iff d is the
 (log_e a)th digit (counting from the right, starting with 0)
 in the base-e expansion of n:}
DIG(a,e,d,n) :=
   (d < e) & Eb:Ec:((c < a) & (n = (b*e*a) + (d*a) + c))

{if e is prime, and a is a power of e, true iff n has exactly
 (log_e a) digits in its base-e expansion (0 is counted as having 0
 digits:}
LENGTH(e,a,n):=
   (n < a) & Ab:((PPOWER(b,e) & (b < a)) -> (b <= n))

POWER_OF_TEN(x):=
   Ee:(PRIME(e) & (e > x) &
       En:Ea:(LENGTH(e,a,n) &
              DIG(1,e,1,n) &
              Ai:Aj:Au:(  (PPOWER(u,e) & ((e*u) < a)
			   & DIG(u,e,i,n) & DIG(e*u,e,j,n))
                          -> j = (10 * i)  ) &
              Eu:(PPOWER(u,e) & (e*u = a) & DIG(u,e,x,n))
       )     )

The basic idea is that you are asserting that for some prime e greater
than x, we can find a number n which, when expressed in base-e notation,
will have 1 in its units place, 10 in its e's place, 100 in its (e^2)'s
place, and in general have the "digit" in each place be 10 times
greater than the one to its right, such that the leftmost digit is our x.

To translate into Hofstadter's notation, of course, we must use horse-shoes
instead of ->'s, big carets instead of &'s, letters a through e (followed
by however many ''s) exclusively, and so forth. (We must also replace <'s
and <= with appropriate expansions, and substitute in for our capitalized
formula abbreviations.) This is left as an exercise to the reader.

Kevin Wald
wald2@husc.harvard.edu

==> logic/hundred.p <==
A sheet of paper has statements numbered from 1 to 100.  Statement n says
"exactly n of the statements on this sheet are false."  Which statements are
true and which are false?  What if we replace "exactly" by "at least"?

==> logic/hundred.s <==
From _Litton's Problematical Recreations_

It is tempting to argue as follows:

At most one statement can be true (they are mutually contradictory).
If they are all false, statement 100 would be true, which is no good.
So 99 are false, and statement 99 is true.

If replaced by "at least", and the "real" number of false statements is
x, then statements x+1 to 100 will be false (since they falsely claim
that there are more false statements than there actually are). So, 100-x are 
false, ie.  x=100-x, so x=50. The first 50 statements are true, and statements
51 to 100 are false. 

However, there is a hidden and incorrect assumption in this argument.
To see this, suppose that there is one statement on the sheet and it
says "One statement is false"  or "At least one statement is false,"
either way it implies "this statement is false," which is a familiar
paradoxical statement.  We have learned that this paradox arises because
of the false assumption that all statements are either true or false.
This is the hidden assumption in the above reasoning.

If it is acknowledged that some of the statements on the page may be
neither true nor false (i.e., meaningless), then nothing whatsoever can
be concluded about which statements are true or false.

This problem has been carefully contrived to appear to be solvable (like
the vacuous statement "this statement is true").  By changing the
numbers in some statements and changing "true" to "false," various
circular forms of the liar's paradox can be constructed.  A much
more complicated version of the same problem is:

 1) At least one of the last two statements in this list is true.

 2) This is either the first true or the first false statement in the
    list.

 3) There exist three consecutive false statements.

 4) The difference beween the numbers of the last true statement and
    the first true statement is a factor of the unknown number.

 5) The sum of the numbers of the true statements is the unknown
    number.

 6) This is not the last true statement.

 7) Each true statement's number is a factor of the unknown number.

 8) The unknown number equals the percentage of these statements which
   are true.

 9) The number of different factors which the unknown number has
   (excluding 1 and itself) is more than the sum of the numbers of the
   true statements.

10) There are no three cosecutive true statements.

What is the number?

The incorrect but plausible solution is:

By 2, either way 1 must be false, and then so must both 9 and 10.

6, if false, says "This is the last true statement", which gives
a paradox, thus 6 must be true, and so must 7 and/or 8.

7 and 8 cannot both be true, as the number had to be a multiple
of 6,7,8 , that is a multiple of 168 (by 7), and less than 100 (by 8)

If 8 is false, then 3 is true (8,9,10 is false), if 8 is true, then
3 is false (3 cannot be true when both 6 and 8 are true, then there
are no three consecutive statements left).

So we have either

A) F X F X X T F T F F
or
B) F X T X X T T F F F

In A), 4 and 5 must be true (by false 10), and 2 may be true or false.
So by 5 the number shall be either 27 (2+3+4+5+6+7) or 25 (3+4+5+6+7).
None of these can fullfill 8, though, so A) is out leaving us with B)

Now, (by 7) 3,6 and 7 are factors, the number must be a multiple of
42, as 2+3+4+5+6+7=27, 5 must be false. 

By false 10, 2 and 4 must be true, that is 5 shall be a multiple
of the number. Now the number must be a multiple of 2,3,4,5,6 and 7,
that is a multiple of 3*4*5*7=420. 420 has 22 different factors
(2,3,4,5,6,7,10,12,14,15,20,21,28,30,35,42,60,70,84,105,140,210)
and the sum 2+3+4+6+7 = 22, so the only multiple of 420 that
fulfills false 9 is 420.

==> logic/inverter.p <==
Can a digital logic circuit with two inverters invert N independent inputs?
The circuit may contain any number of AND or OR gates.

==> logic/inverter.s <==
It can be shown that N inverters can invert 2^N-1 independent inputs,
given an unlimited supply of AND and OR gates. The classic version of
this puzzle is to invert 3 independent inputs using AND gates, OR
gates, and only 2 inverters.

This is solved by:
        n1 = not(i1 and i2 or i1 and i3 or i2 and i3);
        n2 = not((i1 or i2 or i3) and n1  or  i1 and i2 and i3);
        o1 = (i2 or i3 or n2) and n1  or  i2 and i3 and n2;
        o2 = (i1 or i3 or n2) and n1  or  i1 and i3 and n2;
        o3 = (i1 or i2 or n2) and n1  or  i1 and i2 and n2;

i1, i2, and i3 are the inputs, n1 and n2 are the inverted signals, and
o1, o2, and o3 are the outputs.  "and" has higher precedence than "or".

So, start with N inverters.  Replace 3 of them with 2.
Keep doing that until you're down to 2 inverters.

I was skeptical at first, because such a design requires so much feedback
that I was sure the system would oscillate when switching between two
particular states.  But after writing a program to test every possible state 
change (32^2), it appears that this system settles after a maximum of
3 feedback logic iterations. I did not include gate delays in the simulation,
however, which could increase the number of iterations before the system
settles.

In any case, it appears that the world needs only 2 inverters! :-)

==> logic/josephine.p <==
The recent expedition to the lost city of Atlantis discovered scrolls
attributted to the great poet, scholar, philosopher Josephine. They
number eight in all, and here is the first.

THE KINGDOM OF MAMAJORCA, WAS RULED BY QUEEN HENRIETTA I. IN MAMAJORCA
WOMEN HAVE TO PASS AN EXTENSIVE LOGIC EXAM BEFORE THEY ARE ALLOWED TO
GET MARRIED. QUEENS DO NOT HAVE TO TAKE THIS EXAM. ALL THE WOMEN IN
MAMAJORCA ARE LOYAL TO THEIR QUEEN AND DO WHATEVER SHE TELLS THEM TO.
THE QUEENS OF MAMAJORCA ARE TRUTHFUL. ALL SHOTS FIRED IN MAMAJORCA CAN
BE HEARD IN EVERY HOUSE. ALL ABOVE FACTS ARE KNOWN TO BE COMMON
KNOWLEDGE.

HENRIETTA WAS WORRIED ABOUT THE INFIDELITY OF THE MARRIED MEN IN
MAMAJORCA.  SHE SUMMONED ALL THE WIVES TO THE TOWN SQUARE, AND MADE
THE FOLLOWING ANNOUNCEMENT. "THERE IS AT LEAST ONE UNFAITHFUL HUSBAND
IN MAMAJORCA. ALL WIVES KNOW WHICH HUSBANDS ARE UNFAITHFUL, BUT HAVE
NO KNOWLEDGE ABOUT THE FIDELITY OF THEIR OWN HUSBAND. YOU ARE
FORBIDDEN TO DISCUSS YOUR HUSBAND'S FAITHFULNESS WITH ANY OTHER WOMAN.
IF YOU DISCOVER THAT YOUR HUSBAND IS UNFAITHFUL, YOU MUST SHOOT HIM AT
PRECISELY MIDNIGHT OF THE DAY YOU FIND THAT OUT."

THIRTY-NINE SILENT NIGHTS FOLLOWED THE QUEEN'S ANNOUNCEMENT. ON THE
FORTIETH NIGHT, SHOTS WERE HEARD. QUEEN HENRIETTA I IS REVERED IN
MAMAJORCAN HISTORY.

As with all philosophers Josephine doesn't provide the question, but leaves
it implicit in his document. So figure out the questions - there are two -
and answer them.

Here is Josephine's second scroll.

QUEEN HENRIETTA I WAS SUCCEEDED BY DAUGHTER QUEEN HENRIETTA II. AFTER
A WHILE HENRIETTA LIKE HER FAMOUS MOTHER BECAME WORRIED ABOUT THE
INFIDELITY PROBLEM. SHE DECIDED TO ACT, AND SENT A LETTER TO HER
SUBJECTS (WIVES) THAT CONTAINED THE EXACT WORDS OF HENRIETTA I'S
FAMOUS SPEECH.  SHE ADDED THAT THE LETTERS WERE GUARENTEED TO REACH
ALL WIVES EVENTUALLY.

QUEEN HENRIETTA II IS REMEMBERED AS A FOOLISH AND UNJUST QUEEN.

What is the question and answer implied by this scroll?

==> logic/josephine.s <==
The two questions for scroll #1 were:

1. How many husbands were shot on that fateful night?
2. Why is Queen Henrietta I revered in Mamajorca?

The answers are:

If there are n unfaithful husbands (UHs), every wife of an UH knows of
n-1 UH's while every wife of a faithful husband knows of n UHs.  [this
because everyone has perfect information about everything except the
fidelity of their own husband].  Now we do a simple induction: Assume
that there is only one UH.  Then all the wives but one know that there
is just one UH, but the wife of the UH thinks that everyone is
faithful.  Upon hearing that "there is at least one UH", the wife
realizes that the only husband it can be is her own, and so shoots
him.  Now, imagine that there are just two UH's.  Each wife of an UH
assumes that the situation is "only one UH in town" and so waits to
hear the other wife (she knows who it is, of course) shoot her husband
on the first night.  When no one is shot, that can only be because her
OWN husband was a second UH.  The wife of the second UH makes the same
deduction when no shot is fired the first night (she was waiting, and
expecting the other to shoot, too).  So they both figure it out after
the first night, and shoot their husbands the second night.  It is
easy to tidy up the induction to show that the n UHs will all be shot
just on the n'th midnight.

The question for scroll #2 is:

3. Why is Queen Henrietta II not?

The answer is:

The problem now is that QHII didn't realize that it is *critical* that
all of the wives, of faithful and UH's alike, to
*BEGIN*AT*THE*SAME*MOMENT*.  The uncertainty of having a particular
wife's notice come a day or two late makes the whole logic path fall
apart.  That's why she's foolish.  She is unjust, because some wives,
honed and crack logicians all, remember, will *incorrectly* shoot
faithful husbands.  Let us imagine the situation with just a SINGLE UH
in the whole country.  And, wouldn't you know it, the notice to the
wife of the UH just happens to be held up a day, whereas everyone
else's arrived the first day.  Now, all of the wives that got the
notice the first day know that there is just one UH in the country.
And they know that the wife of that UH will think that everyone is
faithful, and so they'll expect her to figure it out and shoot her
husband the first night.  BUT SHE DIDN"T GET THE NOTICE THE FIRST
NIGHT....  BUT THE OTHER WIVES HAVE NO WAY OF KNOWING THAT.  So, the
wife of the UH doesn't know that anything is going on and so (of
course) doesn't do anything the first night.  The next day she gets
the notice, figures it all out, and her husband will be history come
that midnight.  BUT... *every* other wife thought that there should
have been a shooting the first night, and since there wasn't there
must have been an additional UH, and it can only have been _her_
husband.  So on the second night **ALL** of the husbands are shot.
Things are much more complicated if the mix of who gets the notice
when is less simple than the one I mentioned above, but it is always
wrong and/or tragic.

NOTE: if the wives *know* that the country courier service (or however
these things get delivered) is flaky, then they can avoid the
massacre, but unless the wives exchange notes no one will ever be shot
(since there is always a chance that rather than _your_ husband being
an UH, you could reason that it might be that the wife of one of the
UH's that you know about just hasn't gotten her copy of the scroll
yet).  I guess you could call this case "unjust", too, since the UH's
evade punishment, despite the perfect logic of the wives.

==> logic/locks.and.boxes.p <==
You want to send a valuable object to a friend.  You have a box which
is more than large enough to contain the object.  You have several
locks with keys.  The box has a locking ring which is more than large enough
to have a lock attached.  But your friend does not have the key to any
lock that you have.  How do you do it?  Note that you cannot send a key
in an unlocked box, since it might be copied.


==> logic/locks.and.boxes.s <==
Attach a lock to the ring.  Send it to her.  She attaches her own lock
and sends it back.  You remove your lock and send it back to her.  She
removes her lock.

==> logic/min.max.p <==
In a rectangular array of people, which will be taller, the tallest of the
shortest people in each column, or the shortest of the tallest people in each row?

==> logic/min.max.s <==
Let T denote shortest of tall
Let S denote tallest of short

-------------------------------
|                             |
|                             |
|                S            |
|                             |
|                             |
|    T           X            |
|                             |
|                             |
|                             |
|                             |
-------------------------------

So T >= X >= S.


==> logic/mixing.p <==
Start with a half cup of tea and a half cup of coffee. Take one tablespoon
of the tea and mix it in with the coffee. Take one tablespoon of this mixture
and mix it back in with the tea. Which of the two cups contains more of its
original contents?

==> logic/mixing.s <==
Mixing Liquids

The two cups end up with the same volume of liquid they started with. The same
amount of tea was moved to the coffee cup as coffee to the teacup. Therefore
each cup contains the same amount of its original contents.

==> logic/monty.52.p <==
Monty and Waldo play a game with N closed boxes.  Monty hides a
dollar in one box; the others are empty.  Monty opens the empty boxes
one by one.  When there are only two boxes left Waldo opens either box;
he wins if it contains the dollar.  Prior to each of the N-2 box
openings Waldo chooses one box and locks it, preventing Monty from opening
it next.  That box is then unlocked and cannot be so locked twice in a row.

What are the optimal strategies for Monty and Waldo and what is the
fair price for Waldo to pay to play the game?

==> logic/monty.52.s <==
The fair price for large N is $0.6321205588285576784; I will offer
a proof along with optimal strategies.

Denote the game as G_N().  After (N-M) rounds of play, the game will have
the same form as G_M().  Depending on the strategies each of the M boxes
will have a probability p_i of containing the dollar.  Let Waldo lock
the M'th box (renumbering the boxes if necessary).  Denote the game and
Waldo's expected winnings in the game by
		G_M(p_1, p_2, ..., p_M)
where
		p_1 + p_2 + ... + p_M = 1

When
		p_2 = p_3 = p_4 = ... = p_M
we adopt the abbreviation
		G_M(b) = G_M(1 + b - Mb, b, b, b, b, ..., b)
and note that since probabilities are never negative:
		1 + b - Mb >= 0, or
		0 <= b <= 1 / (M-1)

Various G_M(p_1, p_2, ..., p_M) have difficult solutions but we are asked
only to solve G_M(1/M) and it turns out we can accomplish this by
considering only the games
		G_M(b)  where	1/M  <=  b  <=  1/(M-1)		[1]
Games of this form will be said to satisfy constraint [1].

Induction is used for one of the theorems, so we'd better solve G_2 and G_3
for our basis.
		G_2(p_1, p_2) = max (p_1, p_2)
		G_3(p_1, p_2, p_3) = max (p_1 + p_2, p_3)
since after Monty opens box #1, box #2 will have probability (p_1 + p_2)
and vice versa.  When the probabilities satisfy constraint [1]: 
		G_2(b) = G_2(1-b, b) = b
		G_3(b) = G_3(1-2b, b, b) = 1 - b

The proof of Theorem 1 is based on the probability p_i that box #i
contains the dollar.  (Of course this is Waldo's perceived probability:
Monty's probability would be 0 or 1.)  It may seem wrong for Waldo to
"forget" the game history and remember only the computed p_i.  For
example he may have previously locked some but not all of the boxes
and this fact is ignored except in the calculation of p_i.  Or Monty may
have some higher level "plan" which mightn't seem to translate directly
into probabilities.  But probability algebra obeys some simplifying
linearity rules and, if Monty keeps a "poker face", the probability model
is the only thing Waldo has to act on.

Especially paradoxical is the derivation of Waldo's p_i in his trivial
strategy below: he can adopt inferior but "correct" p_i to simplify the
analysis.

Theorem 1)
	If   b >= 1/M   then
	G_M(b) = G_[M-1]( (1-b) / (M-2) )

Proof)
	We will show that Monty and Waldo each have a strategy in G_M(b) to
	reduce the game to G_[M-1](b, q, q, ..., q) where q = (1-b) / (M-2)
	and where the boxes have been renumbered so that box #1 was box #M
	(the one Waldo locked) from the prior round and the new box #(M-1)
	is the one Waldo locks next.  Note that if Monty indeed arranges
	the probability mixture G_[M-1](b, q, q, q, q, ..., q) it won't
	matter which box Waldo locks (Box #1 has the only non-equal
	probability but Waldo cannot lock the same box twice in a row);
	this is a typical property of "saddlepoint" strategy.

	We will derive the necessary and sufficient condition for Monty to
	reduce any game G_M(p_1, p_2, p_3, ..., p_M) to a single game with
	the form G_[M-1](b, q, q, ..., q).  Using the numbering of G_M()
	let R(i,j) be the joint probability that Box #i contains the dollar
	and Box #j is opened by Monty in G_M().  We need consider only
		M >= 3
	Clearly,
		R(i, j) >= 0
		R(i, i) = 0
		R(i, M) = 0, i < M
		sum_over_j R(i,j) = p_i
	and to achieve q_2 = q_3 = ... = q_[M-1] in G_[M-1],
		R(1, j) = R(k, j)
			for 1 < j,k < M and j != k
		R(2, 1) = R(k, 1)
			for 2 < k < M
	and to make G_[M-1] be independent of Monty's play
		R(M, j)/R(1, j) = R(M, 2)/R(1, 2)
			for 2 < j < M
		R(M, 2)/R(1, 2) = R(M, 1)/R(2, 1)

	The above have a simple unique solution:
		R(i, j) = (1 - p_M) / (M - 2)  - p_j		[2]
			for i,j < M and i != j
		R(M, j) = p_M - p_j * p_M / (1 - p_M)		[3]
			for j < M
		p_j * (M-2) + p_M <= 1				[4]

	For the theorem we are given that G_M(b) satisfies constraint [1]
		1 / M  <=  b  <=  1 / (M - 1)
	which implies the weaker inequality
		(M - 3) / (M^2 - 3M + 1)  <=  b  <=  1 / (M - 1)
	and since for the constraint-[1] compliant G_M()
		p_j = b   or   p_j = (1+b-Mb)   for all j
	the inequality [4] follows directly.

	Hence Monty can transpose G_M(b) into G_[M-1]( (1-b) / (M-2) )
	whenever b >= 1/M and M >= 3.  (This G_[M-1] also happens to
	satisfy constraint [1] as needed for the next theorem.)

	It should be easy to argue that this strategy is optimal for Monty,
	but we want to derive Waldo's best strategy anyway and if it
	guarantees the same value we know we're at the "saddlepoint".
	If Waldo knows Monty has a non-optimal strategy he can take
	advantage of it, but we will just derive a strategy good enough
	to achieve the saddle-point value.

	Monty must transform G_M(b) into some
		G_[M-1](b, q_2, q_3, ..., q_[M-1])
	where Waldo has the choice of locking any of boxes #2 through #(M-1).
	If Waldo locks each of the (M-2) available boxes with probability
	1/(M-2) it is easily seen that the average probability that he
	locks the box with the dollar is (1-b) / (M-2) and the probabilities
	q_2, q_3, ..., q_[M-2] will also have the average value (1-b)/(M-2).
	If Waldo pretends to "forget" which box he picked before, he can
	take q_2 = q_3 = ... = (1-b)/(M-2) thereby constructing the same
	game Monty constructed with his saddlepoint strategy!

	In the above Waldo in effect "degraded" the accuracy of his
	probability estimates with the substitutions
		q_2' = (q_2 + q_3 + ... + q_[M-1]) / (M - 2)
		q_3' = (q_2 + q_3 + ... + q_[M-1]) / (M - 2)
		  et cetera
	If Waldo "knows" more than this, he can pretend he doesn't!
	For example he can ask Monty to secretly shuffle the boxes.

	Thus either player can reduce
		G_M(b), b >= 1/M
	to
		G_[M-1]((1-b)/(M-2))
	so this must be the saddlepoint.
	Q.E.D.

Theorem 2)
	If   b >= 1/M   then
	G_M(b) = 1 - 1/2! + 1/3! - ... - (1-b)(-1)^M/(M-2)!
		= - sum (-1)^i/i! - (1-b)(-1)^M/(M-2)!
	where the sum is over i = 1, 2, 3, ..., M-3

Proof)
	The proof is by induction.  We know the theorem holds for M = 3
	and we will assume it holds for (M-1).  Set
		c = (1-b) / (M-2)
	We noted earlier that b <= 1/(M-1): otherwise p_1 = (1 + b - Mb)
	is negative; hence we obtain
		c = (1-b)/(M-2) >= (1 - 1/(M-1)) / (M-2)
	or simply
		c >= 1/(M-1)
	Thus the condition of the inductive hypothesis is satisfied and
		G_[M-1](c) = 1 - 1/2! + 1/3! - ... + (1-c)(-1)^M/(M-3)!
	But from Theorem 1
		G_M(b) = G_[M-1](c)
	and from the definition of c,
		c/(M-3)! = (1-b)/(M-2)!
	which establishes the theorem.

Theorem 3)
	G_M(1/M) = G_M(1/M, ..., 1/M) = 1 - 1/2! + 1/3! - ... -(-1)^M/M!

Proof)
	This follows directly from Theorem 2 and the observation that
		(1/M)/(M-2)! = 1/(M-1)! - 1/M!

For large M, G_M(1/M) approaches (1 - 1/e).  It will be a little bigger
when M is odd and a little smaller when M is even.  I've appended the
numeric values below.

% dc
[[Solution for M =]Plb1+pdsb]sy
65k1sa1sblyx2sc[la1lc/-dsaplclyx*scla1lc/+dsaplclyx*sclzx]dszx
Solution for M =2
0.50000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000
Solution for M =3
0.66666666666666666666666666666666666666666666666666666666666666666
Solution for M =4
0.62500000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000
Solution for M =5
0.63333333333333333333333333333333333333333333333333333333333333333
Solution for M =6
0.63194444444444444444444444444444444444444444444444444444444444445
Solution for M =7
0.63214285714285714285714285714285714285714285714285714285714285714
Solution for M =8
0.63211805555555555555555555555555555555555555555555555555555555556
Solution for M =9
0.63212081128747795414462081128747795414462081128747795414462081129
Solution for M =10
0.63212053571428571428571428571428571428571428571428571428571428572
	. . .
Solution for M =52
0.63212055882855767840447622983853913255418886896823216549216319831

P. S. There are related unsolved problems:
(a) what about G_M(p_1, p_2, ..., p_M) that do not fit the pattern used
in the above solution?
(b) what if two boxes contain dollars?  (first, what should the rules be?)

-- james@crc.ricoh.com (James Allen)

==> logic/number.p <==
Mr. S. and Mr. P. are both perfect logicians, being able to correctly deduce
any truth from any set of axioms.  Two integers (not necessarily unique) are
somehow chosen such that each is within some specified range.  Mr. S.
is given the sum of these two integers; Mr. P. is given the product of these
two integers.  After receiving these numbers, the two logicians do not
have any communication at all except the following dialogue:
<<1>>   Mr. P.:  I do not know the two numbers.
<<2>>   Mr. S.:  I knew that you didn't know the two numbers.
<<3>>   Mr. P.:  Now I know the two numbers.
<<4>>   Mr. S.:  Now I know the two numbers.

Given that the above statements are absolutely truthful, what are the two
numbers?

==> logic/number.s <==
The answer depends upon the ranges from which the numbers are chosen.

The unique solution for the ranges [2,62] through [2,500+] is:

  SUM   PRODUCT   X   Y
   17      52     4  13

The unique solution for the ranges [3,94] through [3,500+] is:

  SUM   PRODUCT   X   Y
   29     208    13  16

There are no unique solutions for the ranges starting with 1,
and there are no solutions for ranges starting with numbers above 3.

A program to compute the possible pairs is included below.

#include <stdio.h>

/*

BEGINNING OF PROBLEM STATEMENT:
Mr. S. and Mr. P. are both perfect logicians, being able to correctly deduce
any truth from any set of axioms.  Two integers (not necessarily unique) are
somehow chosen such that each is within some specified range.  Mr. S.
is given the sum of these two integers; Mr. P. is given the product of these
two integers.  After receiving these numbers, the two logicians do not
have any communication at all except the following dialogue:
<<1>>   Mr. P.:  I do not know the two numbers.
<<2>>   Mr. S.:  I knew that you didn't know the two numbers.
<<3>>   Mr. P.:  Now I know the two numbers.
<<4>>   Mr. S.:  Now I know the two numbers.

Given that the above statements are absolutely truthful, what are the two
numbers?

END OF PROBLEM STATEMENT

 */

#define SMALLEST_MIN	1
#define LARGEST_MIN	10
#define SMALLEST_MAX	50
#define LARGEST_MAX	500

long P[(LARGEST_MAX + 1) * (LARGEST_MAX + 1)];		/* products */
long S[(LARGEST_MAX + 1) + (LARGEST_MAX + 1)];		/*   sums   */

find(long min, long max)
{
	long i, j;
	/*
	 *	count factorizations in P[]
	 *	all P[n] > 1 satisfy <<1>>.
	 */
	for(i = 0; i <= max * max; ++i)
		P[i] = 0;

	for(i = min; i <= max; ++i)
		for(j = i; j <= max; ++j)
			++P[i * j];

	/*
	 *	decompose possible SUMs and check factorizations
	 *		all S[n] == min - 1 satisfy <<2>>.
	 */
	for(i = min + min; i <= max + max; ++i) {

		for(j = i / 2; j >= min; --j)
			if(P[j * (i - j)] < 2)
				break;

		S[i] = j;
	}

	/*
	 *	decompose SUMs which satisfy <<2>> and see which products
	 *	they produce.  All (P[n] / 1000 == 1) satisfy <<3>>.
	 */
	for(i = min + min; i <= max + max; ++i)
		if(S[i] == min - 1)
			for(j = i / 2; j >= min; --j)
				if(P[j * (i - j)] > 1)
					P[j * (i - j)] += 1000;
	/*
	 *	decompose SUMs which satisfy <<2>> again and see which products
	 *	satisfy <<3>>.  Any (S[n] == 999 + min) satisfies <<4>>
	 */
	for(i = min + min; i <= max + max; ++i)
		if(S[i] == min - 1)
			for(j = i / 2; j >= min; --j)
				if(P[j * (i - j)] / 1000 == 1)
					S[i] += 1000;
	/*
	 *	find the answer(s) and print them
	 */
	printf("[%d,%d]\n",min,max);
	for(i = min + min; i <= max + max; ++i)
		if(S[i] == 999 + min)
			for(j = i / 2; j >= min; --j)
				if(P[j * (i - j)] / 1000 == 1)
					printf("{ %d %d }: S = %d, P = %d\n",
						i - j, j, i, (i - j)  * j);
}

main()
{
	long min, max;

	for (min = SMALLEST_MIN; min <= LARGEST_MIN; min ++)
	    for (max = SMALLEST_MAX; max <= LARGEST_MAX; max++)
		find(min,max);
}

-------------------------------------------------------------------------
=			Jeff Kenton	(617) 894-4508			=
=			    jkenton@world.std.com			=
-------------------------------------------------------------------------

User Contributions:

[url="https://adobe.com/"]Adobe Lightroom[/url] is the most conventional essence editing software with a view the purpose photographers, with hundreds of thousands of effects and presets within reach on the internet.

You can download Lightroom from Adobes website.

[url="https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Adobe_Lightroom"]Adobe Lightroom[/url] presets help you to clean up your photos in register term about doing a lot of the work for you. You can plainly essay away from a pre-defined capacity, while keeping your source impression and reverting following to it at anytime.

You can use:
Lightroom Presets for Wedding Photography
Lightroom Presets for Baby and Family Photography
Lightroom Presets for Headshots
Lightroom Presets for Senior Portraits
Lightroom Presets for Landscape
Lightroom Presets for Nature Photography
Lightroom Presets for Food Photography
Lightroom Presets for Car Photography
Lightroom Presets for Real Estate
Lightroom Presets for Product and Fashion Photography

And a [url="https://mrlightroom.com/shop/lightroom-presets/dreamy-lightroom-desktop-and-mobile-presets/"]Dreamy Lightroom Desktop and Mobile Presets[/url]
for everyday shooting.
[url="https://adobe.com/"]Adobe Lightroom[/url] is the most controlling image editing software because the drive photographers, with hundreds of thousands of effects and presets nearby on the internet.

You can download Lightroom from Adobes website.

[url="https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Adobe_Lightroom"]Adobe Lightroom[/url] presets supporter you to crop your photos in register but past doing a lot of the piece after you. You can altogether essay out a pre-defined effect, while keeping your source impression and reverting back to it at anytime.

You can use:
Lightroom Presets for Wedding Photography
Lightroom Presets for Baby and Family Photography
Lightroom Presets for Headshots
Lightroom Presets for Senior Portraits
Lightroom Presets for Landscape
Lightroom Presets for Nature Photography
Lightroom Presets for Food Photography
Lightroom Presets for Car Photography
Lightroom Presets for Real Estate
Lightroom Presets for Product and Fashion Photography

And a [url="https://mrlightroom.com/shop/lightroom-presets/dreamy-lightroom-desktop-and-mobile-presets/"]Dreamy Lightroom Desktop and Mobile Presets[/url]
for everyday shooting.
3
Nov 29, 2022 @ 10:22 pm
In problematic times of alteration, there is constantly something good and fine. Quantum medicine - the medicine of the destiny. Hop to - https://t.me/quantummedicinehealy
4
Dec 4, 2022 @ 9:09 am
Yuji Itadori is an unnaturally able capital institute swot living in Sendai. On his deathbed, his grandfather instils two powerful messages within Yuji: "forever help others" and "be no more surrounded close people." Yuji's friends at the The black arts Belabour attracted Curses to their first when they unsealed a rotten pin down b locate parley which Yuji swallowed to safeguard Megumi Fushiguro and their friends, becoming manager to a powerful Curse named Ryomen Sukuna. Payable to Sukuna's treacherous character, all sorcerers are required to exorcise him (and, by way of extension, Yuji) immediately. But upon seeing Yuji retaining control upwards his council, Megumi's master Satoru Gojo brings him to the Tokyo Prefectural Jujutsu High Drill with a programme to his superiors: adjourn Yuji's dying rap and carriage under Satoru until he consumes all of Sukuna's fingers so the Profanity can be eliminated. At the even so set, a rank of cursed spirits plot a multi-layered revile on the world of jujutsu necromancy, including the Cursed spirit Mahito and a corrupted thaumaturgist named Suguru Geto, who was executed close Satoru a year prior. The Kyoto school's supervisor wants Yuji unconcerned immediately at the tit for tat episode between the Tokyo and Kyoto jujutsu schools. In deviate from, others side with Satoru to watch over Yuji alive.
Jujutsu Kaisen read manga online >> https://spotui.com/68-jujutsu-kaisen-chapter-68.html

The disfigured Kyoto Jujutsu Tech second-year student Kokichi Muta, who pilots Mechamaru, is revealed to be a mole. Geto and the cursed spirits air a sort out once again Shibuya. Numerous sorcerers arrive at the stage setting to bickering them. Satoru fights off cursed spirits and exorcises Hanami but is sealed away past Geto in a definite artifact. The events also check that the in circulation Geto is not the prototypical but measure Geto's remains possessed during an venerable sorcerer named Kenjaku. Yuji and his allies face Kenjaku's forces, with Satoru alleviate trapped inside the artifact. As the incident ends, Kenjaku reveals that he has been jumping from trunk to body an eye to thousands of years and implanting Binding Vows, which in avert awakens thousands of rejuvenated sorcerers throughout Japan, including Tsumiki Fushiguro, Megumi's step-sister. He then unleashes a slew of curses on Japan, ushering in formlessness and a men of cursed spirits reminiscent of the Heian period.
Jujutsu Kaisen read >> https://spotui.com/98-jujutsu-kaisen-chapter-98.html

In the aftermath, Yuji and Megumi band up with second-year swot Yuta Okkotsu and Yuki Tsukumo, a red-letter order jujutsu sorcerer and people of the most powerful sorcerers of all occasion, along with half-human, half-Curse Choso and second-year schoolgirl Maki Zenin to convene with Tengen. Tengen, an famous, part-Curse part-human jujutsu sorcerer, reveals Kenjaku's plan to merge Tengen's consciousness with Japan's forgiving population. The Culling Game, Kenjaku's all-out clash between the sorcerers and Torment users of Japan, then begins.
5
Dec 6, 2022 @ 2:14 pm
It seems remarkable idea to me is
https://thetranny.com/tags/daki/
https://zeenite.com/search/the-first-mfm/
6
Dec 19, 2022 @ 7:07 am
Rather amusing phrase
https://thetranny.com/videos/105188/futanari-asian-girls-sex-in-public-classroom-3d-animation-part-2/
https://thetranny.com/videos/76091/sexy-sissy-cd-sucks-cock-and-swallows-a-lot-of-cum/
7
Jan 2, 2023 @ 6:06 am
https://colab.research.google.com/drive/1pH5bXr6oF7C5WIuE4rN54x9TSMdWi2ED?usp=sharing
https://colab.research.google.com/drive/1fP6RMnG6EbGb7Hld-Dh_2k1jTQ-GvwXN?usp=sharing
https://colab.research.google.com/drive/1fx9pGgQB1j-8NgZbJN5FNh7a5VJnIvUW?usp=sharing
https://colab.research.google.com/drive/1Ydo7wlR3yUHa4PIUqLGbd2MabF-vUAa0?usp=sharing
https://colab.research.google.com/drive/1M50XQXomRIouOrWM5oluBMXIx6bl0GEj?usp=sharing
8
Jan 9, 2023 @ 6:18 pm
https://telegra.ph/Exibindo-A-Buceta-E-O-Cuzinho-11-30
9
Jan 13, 2023 @ 9:21 pm
https://telegra.ph/Does-betonline-have-live-roulette-01-08#Does betonline have live roulette
https://telegra.ph/Live-poker-01-08#Live poker
https://telegra.ph/Casino-online-in-usa-01-08#Casino online in usa
https://telegra.ph/Win2day-live-roulette-01-08#Win2day live roulette
https://telegra.ph/Live-poker-great-falls-montana-01-08#Live poker great falls montana
10
Jan 13, 2023 @ 10:22 pm
Pregnant state info is everywhere. At your own first prenatal visit, your medical professional will likely give you armfuls regarding pamphlets that cover just about every test out and trimester.

Despite all this particular facts, here are 10 frequent surprises this pregnancy can provide.

The Nesting Instinct

Many currently pregnant women feel the nesting instinct, a powerful urge to prepare yourself their home for the baby simply by cleaning and decorating.

As your personal due date draws closer, you might find yourself cleaning cupboards or laundering walls - things you certainly not would have imagined doing in your own personal ninth 30 days of pregnancy! This particular desire to prepare your home can certainly be useful - you'll have got a lot fewer to-do items after the birth. Nevertheless be careful not necessarily to overdo it.

Problems Having Attentiveness

In the first trimester, tiredness as well as morning sickness could make many women experience worn out out and mentally fuzzy. Yet even well-rested pregnant women could have difficulty concentrating and cycles of forgetfulness.

Thinking about the particular baby plays a role, since complete hormonal changes. Everything - like work, bills, and health practitioner sessions - may seem significantly less important compared to baby and typically the coming birth. Making lists can easily help you remember dates along with appointments.

Mood Swings

Premenstrual problem and pregnancy are alike in many ways. Your current breasts get bigger and become tender, your own hormones go up and down, along with you may feel moody. In case you have PMS, you're most likely to have more extreme disposition swings during pregnancy. They can easily make you proceed from being happy one minute to be able to experience like crying the next.

Mood swings are very common during pregnant state. They tend to happen more inside the first trimester in addition to in the direction of the end of the next trimester.

Many pregnant women have got depression while. If you possess symptoms such as sleep complications, changes in eating habits, and mood swings for lengthier than a couple of weeks, talk to your health care provider.

Vettig Size

An increase in breast size is actually one of the first signals of pregnancy. Breast growth in the first trimester is due for you to higher amount hormones estrogen and progesterone. That growth within the initial trimester might not be typically the end, both - your chests can continue to expand during your pregnancy!

Your bra size also can be affected through your ribcage. When you're pregnant, your current lung capacity raises so an individual can take in extra breathable oxygen, that might lead to a bigger chest size. You may want to replace your bras several times during your pregnancy.

Skin area Changes

Do your friends claim you have that pregnancy light? They have one of many outcomes that can come from hormonal changes and your skin stretches.

Pregnant women have increased blood volume to offer extra blood flow to help the uterus and other organs, especially the kidneys. More suitable volume brings more blood to the vessels as well as increases oil human gland secretion.

A number of women develop brownish or becomes yellowish patches called chloasma, or the "mask of pregnancy, very well in their faces. And some will certainly see a dark line upon the midline of the cheaper abdomen, known as often the lista nigra (or linea negra). They will can also have hyperpigmentation (darkening with the skin) of the hard nips, external genitalia, and anal place. That's because pregnancy hormones cause the body to create more color.

This increased color might not really be even, so the dim skin may appear as splotches of colouring. Chloasma can't always be prevented, but using sunscreen and also avoiding UV light source can lessen its effects.

Acne is common in the course of pregnancy because the sk (...)
11
Jan 27, 2023 @ 2:02 am
https://spaplanet.net/pl/services-category/us-ugi/hammam-pl/
12
Feb 2, 2023 @ 7:19 pm
https://colab.research.google.com/drive/1Yp2vGngIdkyNHQ_bu4CaW4sUtka9Y_rY?usp=sharing
https://colab.research.google.com/drive/1ZlSA1bdxAHjo388ub611olrSl9-Vfk6c?usp=sharing
https://colab.research.google.com/drive/1TVIZW7pMu2Ze37Mlq9OOpFrv1ugIBA2v?usp=sharing
https://colab.research.google.com/drive/1ZsxEOjbspxhCB8rq6qoxg0u-eLfSyKdr?usp=sharing
https://colab.research.google.com/drive/1YX1UkHyXx1vi2_JmSHCFpEDTY8cwkAXW?usp=sharing
13
Feb 12, 2023 @ 10:10 am
ts0HrzEscL0Q3xXANksfbEzHXh2U7tCt
hTzkrbPRTEHwNy8SXdOzHAesd1HyU9mx
08duWbBBw3cQ03gvhHuaZkhQ4UcAi9d9
8g3aBVcXBcdzHxejW5SFIvCsM2L2JTPC
CMLZF7uG6ibAqmRqqEk3ZzkcqB7nWqAT
lJsobNZCUCjXcVEWTKsB3IasPNwZVsJu
ZByPKbTFVeLg2wxTyrcYIe4fysCH08uV
yLwplwYtay7cC6v3IpMyKZhu00buDpev
14
Feb 12, 2023 @ 10:10 am
Jean, his mother's younger sister, arrived at the dynasty fair and at daybreak on Saturday morning.

"Hi squirt," she said. Rick didn't resent the slate it was a epithet she had given him when he was born. At the tempo, she was six and thought the name was cute. They had every time been closer than most nephews and aunts, with a normal little bit of skirt notion process she felt it was her duty to help accept misery of him. "Hi Jean," his female parent and he said in unison. "What's up?" his mommy added.

"Don't you two remember, you promised to ease me take some stuff visible to the storage shed at Mom and Dad's farm. Didn't you attired in b be committed to some too Terri?"

"Oh, I quite forgot, but it doesn't occasion for it's all separated in the finance bedroom." She turned to her son. "Can you employees Rick?"

"Yeah," He said. "I've got nothing planned for the day. Tod's out of village and Jeff is sick in bed, so there's no rhyme to hang pass‚ with."

As husky as Rick was, it was still a an enormous number of work to burden the bed, chest and boxes from his aunts business and from his own into the pickup. At the last moment after two hours they were ready to go. Rick covered the load, because it looked like rain and even had to shake up a pair of the boxes inside the sundries background it on the bum next to Jean.

"You're succeeding to suffer with to remain on Rick's lap," Jean said to Terri, "There won't be sufficiently office otherwise."

"That will be alright, won't it Rick?" his mummy said.

"Fit as extensive as you don't weigh a ton, and peculate up the whole side of the odds," he said laughing.

"I'll enjoy you positive I weigh a specific hundred and five pounds, minor humanity, and I'm just five foot three, not six foot three." She was grinning when she said it, but there was a dwarf scrap of joy in her voice. At thirty-six, his progenitrix had the trunk and looks of a high adherents senior. Although few high school girls had 36C boobs that were brimming, undeviating and had such prominent nipples, together with a gang ten ass. Profession his distinction to her body was not the pre-eminent doodad she could have done.

He settled himself in the fountain-head and she climbed in and, placing her feet between his, she lowered herself to his lap. She was wearing a scrawny summer dress and he had seen sole a bikini panty pursuit and bra under it. He instanter felt the enthusiasm from her body flow into his crotch area. He turned his viewpoint to the means ahead. Jean pulled away, and moments later they were on the wilderness approach to the lease, twenty miles away.
https://hentai0day.com/videos/6211/professor-teaches-student-in-apron-a-hard-lesson-eng-subs/
15
Mar 18, 2023 @ 2:14 pm
https://telegra.ph/Casinos-online-malta-01-08#Casinos online malta
https://telegra.ph/Zar-casinos-online-01-08#Zar casinos online
https://telegra.ph/Havaianas-brasil-slim-branca-01-08#Havaianas brasil slim branca
https://telegra.ph/Casino-online-play-01-08#Casino online play
https://telegra.ph/High-stakes-live-poker-01-08#High stakes live poker
16
Apr 8, 2023 @ 2:14 pm
Hey guys,

I'm trying to sell my house fast in Colorado and I was wondering if anyone had any tips or suggestions on how to do it quickly and efficiently? I've already tried listing it on some popular real estate websites, but I haven't had much luck yet.

I've heard that staging my home can help it sell faster, but I'm not sure if it's worth the investment.

If anyone has any experience with selling a house fast in Colorado, I would love to hear your story.

Thanks in advance!

Comment about this article, ask questions, or add new information about this topic:




Part1 - Part2 - Part3 - Part4 - Part5

[ Usenet FAQs | Web FAQs | Documents | RFC Index ]

Send corrections/additions to the FAQ Maintainer:
archive-comment@questrel.com





Last Update March 27 2014 @ 02:12 PM